Read Your Way to Truth, Knowledge, and Freedom.

“Girl Reading,” by Vera Alabaster, 20th Century, Harbour Cottage Trust (Art UK, 2021)


You can also download and read or share a .pdf of the complete text of this essay by scrolling down to the bottom of the post and clicking on the Download tab.


Read Your Way to Truth, Knowledge, and Freedom

There is an absolute contradiction between the freedom we all presuppose in practice and the implications of ideas that are widely accepted as established scientific fact. Philosophy has no higher calling than to try to resolve this contradiction at the heart of contemporary culture. (Griffin, 1998: p. 171)

As per the epigraph directly above, in the late 20th century D.R. Griffin correctly pointed out that “[p]hilosophy has no higher calling” than “to try to resolve [the] absolute contradiction” that on the one hand, (i) we presuppose the existence of real free will in all our everyday choices, actions, morality, and sociopolitics, yet on the other hand, (ii) our contemporary formal-&-natural sciences and the scientistic[i] philosophy that apes these, all tell us that we’re really nothing but deterministic or indeterministic machines and therefore not really free. In order to resolve that paradox, in this essay I’ll argue that just by virtue of your reading a certain sentence, it necessarily follows that you possess real free will. From that, it also necessarily follows that contemporary formal-&-natural sciences and philosophy must explicitly incorporate the primitive fact of our real free will into their conception of the natural universe.

As per (Hanna, 2023a: p. 6, 2023b: p. 2), let’s call any sentence that is (i) specifically about the act or process of reading, and that is also (ii) self-referring by means of the 2nd person indexical description “you, the reader,” and the indexical description “this very sentence,” a caveat lector sentence. Such sentences are so-named by me after the Latin phrase “caveat lector,” meaning let the reader beware; but I’m interpreting that phrase broadly enough so as also to include the meaning let the reader be self-consciously aware. Here is a paradigmatic example of a caveat lector sentence:

You, the reader of this very sentence, are consciously reading this very sentence from left to right here and now.

For convenience, I’ll call the sentence I displayed in boldface text immediately above,

THE SENTENCE

and for the purposes of this essay, it won’t matter whether THE SENTENCE is a universal sentence-type or a particular sentence-token.

Dear Reader, please now read THE SENTENCE again, this time (even) more slowly and carefully.

Obviously, insofar as you read THE SENTENCE, it’s true. What do I mean by “true”? First, by a veridical appearance I mean anything X that appears as F, or appears F-ly, or appears to be F, to any or all rational human animals, just insofar as, and precisely because, X is F. Second, by the manifestly real world, I mean the world as it can veridically appear, or does veridically appear, to any or all rational human animals. Then, third, a statement (judgment, belief, proposition, meaningful sentence, etc.) is true if and only if what it states (means, says, etc.) is manifestly real.

Moreover, your belief that THE SENTENCE is true is sufficiently justified by the intrinsically compelling evidence that is yielded by the phenomenology—i.e., the subjectively experienced intentional performance, intentional content, and specific qualitative characters—of your conscious act or process of reading it. THE SENTENCE cannot read itself, because it’s not conscious; and nobody else but you consciously read that very sentence in the same way, at the same time, and in the same place, that you did. On the contrary to both of those, because THE SENTENCE is in English you consciously read it from left to right, and you also consciously read it right here and now, just as the sentence says. Even if nothing else in the world had existed but that sentence and your consciously reading it from left to right here and now; even if you had consciously read that sentence in a dream; or even if an evil scientist had somehow produced in you a hallucination of your consciously reading that sentence: it would still be true, and your belief in its truth would still be sufficiently justified by the intrinsically compelling evidence yielded by the phenomenology of your conscious act or process of reading it. Thus there are no epistemic gaps between you, the reader of THE SENTENCE, and your consciously reading that very sentence. Or otherwise put, the connection between (i) the evidence for your belief in THE SENTENCE and (ii) the truth of your belief in THE SENTENCE, is not accidental or contingent, and extrinsic, but at the very least fully reliable or even strictly necessary, and intrinsic: thus that evidential process is inherently truth-tracking. So you have authentic, skepticism-proof, empirical or a posteriori knowledge of THE SENTENCE (see also Hanna, 2015: esp. section 1.7). Or in René Descartes’s technical terminology, you have clear, distinct, and certain intuitive knowledge of it (Descartes, 1984-1985a, 1984-1985b, 1984-1985d, 1984-1985e).   

Granting all that, then what I want to argue is that just by virtue of your reading THE SENTENCE and thereby having authentic knowledge of it, it necessarily follows that you possess real free will.

What is real free will? Real free will is an objective fact about the natural universe, and not merely something psychological—for example, a belief in free will or a consciousness of free will. In principle, those could exist even if real free will didn’t. Nevertheless, real free will does also include a rich psychological aspect: namely, capacities for consciousness, self-consciousness, desires, and choices. And if the capacity for rationality is added to those capacities, then it’s also possible to believe in free will. Fully explicitly now, something X has real free will if and only if (i) X is a certain kind of complex living organism, namely an animal, and not a machine, whether this machine is a deterministic automaton, whose behaviors are necessitated by all the settled facts about the past, together with the laws of nature, or an indeterministic automaton, whose behaviors occur according to probabilistic or statistical laws, and are always more or less random, (ii) X is conscious, i.e., X has a capacity for subjective experiences, that is also at least sometimes actualized, (iii) X is self-conscious, i.e., X has a capacity for being conscious of its own subjectively experiential acts, processes, or  states, that is also at least sometimes actualized, (iv) X really can consciously &/or self-consciously choose and do what X desires to choose and do, or consciously &/or self-consciously refrain from so choosing and so doing, without being in any way compelled or prevented by irresistible inner or outer forces, and (v) X has a live option LO, which means that (v.1) X can commit themselves to choosing or doing LO, or not, (or: X could have committed themselves to choosing or doing LO, or not), (v.2) LO would never actually happen unless X were to choose it or do it, (or: LO would never have actually happened unless X had chosen it or done it), and (v.3) X actually chooses and does LO, or not (or: X actually chose and did LO, or not).

In short, X is an intentional agent, and according to my view, intentional agency is equally non-deterministic and non-indeterministic, precisely because it’s purposive and self-organizing, or internally and spontaneously goal-oriented and organismic or non-mechanical, and also includes a live option. In the jargon of contemporary metaphysics of free will, this collectively yields a neo-organicist version of source incompatibilism without alternative possibilities (Hanna, 2018: ch. 5). This means that it’s metaphysically impossible for any agent to have real free will and also to be either a deterministic or indeterministic automaton (incompatibilism). Moreover, if X also has a capacity for rationality—namely, a complex capacity for logical inference, for practical decision-making, and for formulating, recognizing, and being guided by rules, principles, and instrumental or non-instrumental ideals, standards, and values (see, e.g., Hanna, 2006, 2015)— then by virtue of having rationality + free will, not only is X an intentional agent, non-deterministic, non-indeterministic, purposive, organismic or non-mechanical, and the possessor of a live option, but also X is a rational agent, who is the ultimate source—against the metaphysical backdrop of source incompatibilism without alternative possibilities—of their really free choices and actions, for which they are causally and morally responsible. For a detailed and extended argument that the preceding analysis of real free will is not only conceptually intelligible but also rationally defensible and correct, see (Hanna and Maiese, 2009; Hanna, 2018: chs. 1-5, 2020, 2023c, 2024a, 2024b: esp. chs. 1, 3, 5 and 15).

Now, I’ll prove that just by virtue of your reading THE SENTENCE and thereby having authentic knowledge of it, it necessarily follows that you possess real free will, in seven steps.

1.  If a true belief were brought about by a deterministic evidential process, then that belief could just as easily have been false: given all the settled facts about the past together with the laws of nature, the belief would have come about in any case, whether it were true or false; hence a deterministic evidential process is never inherently truth-tracking.

2. If a true belief were brought about an indeterministic evidential process, then that true belief’s existence is or more or less random, and there’s a definite probability that it could have been a false belief; hence an indeterministic evidential process is also never inherently truth-tracking.

3. So if your true belief were brought about by either a deterministic or indeterministic evidential process, then the connection between the evidence for your belief and the truth of your belief is always more or less accidental or contingent, and extrinsic, and not inherently truth-tracking, and therefore that belief is not a sufficiently justified belief, and not authentic knowledge.

4. Therefore, for your authentic knowledge, the evidential process leading to your belief must be neither deterministic nor indeterministic, but instead inherently truth-tracking and caused by your real free will.

5. Just by virtue of your reading THE SENTENCE, you have authentic knowledge of it.

6. Because your knowledge of THE SENTENCE  is authentic knowledge, therefore your belief in it is inherently truth-tracking and caused by your real free will.

7. Therefore, just by virtue of your reading THE SENTENCE and thereby having authentic knowledge of it, it necessarily follows that you have real free will. QED

In other words, without any epistemic or metaphysical fanfare or hullaballoo, you can read your way to truth, knowledge, and freedom. Reading caveat lector sentences is a paradigmatic expression of your capacity for real free will.

As I pointed out at the outset, echoing D.R. Griffin, the fact that we possess real free will has many fundamental consequences for us—existential, moral, and sociopolitical. One of the most important of these is that because, as I’ve just proved, we do indeed possess real free will, then when contemporary formal-&-natural sciences and scientistic philosophy tell us that we’re really nothing but deterministic or indeterministic machines, they’re making a profound mistake. Indeed, in light of my seven-step proof, if either universal natural determinism, or universal natural indeterminism, or the mechanistic worldview more generally, were true, then the holders of those doctrines wouldn’t actually be able to have authentic knowledge of any of those doctrines. And that is of course is self-stultifying, since all of these doctrines are asserted by the holders of those doctrines as knowledge claims.

Therefore, in order to avoid their profound mistake and their self-stultification, and inherently track truth instead, contemporary formal-&-natural sciences and philosophy had better get their acts together, and explicitly incorporate the primitive fact of real free will into their conception of the natural universe (Hanna, 2023c, 2024a, 2024b). You read it here first.

NOTE

[i] Scientism is the dogmatic valorization, especially by philosophers, of the formal-&-natural sciences and their methods. See, e.g., (Haack, 2017; Hanna, 2021: ch XVII).

REFERENCES

(Art UK, 2021). Scavo, G. “Pleasure, Privacy and Power: Reading Women Throughout Art History.” Art UK. 31 March. Available online at URL = <https://artuk.org/discover/stories/pleasure-privacy-and-power-reading-women-throughout-art-history>.

(Descartes, 1984-1985a). Descartes, R. The Philosophical Writings of Descartes. Trans. J. Cottingham, R, Stoothoff, and D. Murdoch. 2 vols., Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press.

(Descartes, 1984-1985b). Descartes, R. Rules for the Direction of the Mind. In (Descartes, 1984-198a: vol. I, pp. 9-78, AT X: 359-472 [1628]).

(Descartes, 1984-1985c). Descartes, R. Discourse on the Method. In (Descartes, 1984-1985a: vol. I, pp. 111-151, AT VI: 1-78 [1637]).

(Descartes, 1984-1985d). Descartes, R. Meditations on First Philosophy. In (Descartes, 1984-1985a: vol. II, pp. 3-62, AT VII: 1-90 [1641]).

(Descartes, 1984-1985e). Descartes, R. Principles of Philosophy. In (Descartes, 1984-1985a: vol. I, pp. 179-291, AT VIIIA: 1-329 [1644]).

(Griffin, 1998). Griffin, D.R. Unsnarling the World-Knot: Consciousness, Freedom, and the Mind-Body Problem. Berkeley CA: Univ. of California Press.

(Haack, 2017). Haack, S. Science and its Discontents. Israel: Rounded Globe. Available online at URL = <https://roundedglobe.com/books/038f7053-e376-4fc3-87c5-096de820966d/Scientism%20and%20its%20Discontents/>.

(Hanna, 2006). Hanna, R. Rationality and Logic. Cambridge: MIT Press. Available online in preview HERE.

(Hanna, 2015). Hanna, R. Cognition, Content, and the A Priori: A Study in the Philosophy of Mind and Knowledge . THE RATIONAL HUMAN CONDITION, Vol. 5. Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press. Available online in preview HERE.

(Hanna, 2018). Hanna, R. Deep Freedom and Real Persons: A Study in Metaphysics. THE RATIONAL HUMAN CONDITION, Vol. 2. New York: Nova Science. Available online in preview HERE.

(Hanna, 2020). Hanna, R. “Will-Power: Essentially Embodied Agentive Phenomenology, By Way of O’Shaughnessy.” In C. Erhard and T. Keiling (eds.), Routledge Handbook: The Phenomenology of Agency. London: Routledge. Pp. 312-333. Available online in preview HERE.

(Hanna, 2021). Hanna, R., The Fate of Analysis: Analytic Philosophy From Frege to The Ash-Heap of History. New York: Mad Duck Coalition. Affordably available in hardcover, softcover, and Epub at URL = <https://themadduckcoalition.org/product/the-fate-of-analysis/>.

(Hanna, 2023a). Hanna, R. “Caveat Lector: From Wittgenstein to The Philosophy of Reading.” Unpublished MS. Available online HERE.

(Hanna, 2023b). Hanna, R. “The Philosophy of Reading as First Philosophy.” Unpublished MS. Available online HERE.

(Hanna, 2023c). Hanna, R. “Free Agency and Quantum Superposition.” Unpublished MS. Available online HERE.

(Hanna, 2024a). Hanna, R. “Let’s Pretend We’re Machines: A New Proof That Real Free Will Exists and That You Really Have It.” Unpublished MS. Available online HERE.

(Hanna, 2024b). Hanna, R. Science For Humans: Mind, Life, The Formal-&-Natural Sciences, and A New Concept of Nature. New York: Springer Nature. Forthcoming.

(Hanna and Maiese, 2009). Hanna, R.  and Maiese, M. Embodied Minds in Action. Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press. Available online in preview HERE.


Against Professional Philosophy is a sub-project of the online mega-project Philosophy Without Borders, which is home-based on Patreon here.

Please consider becoming a patron!