“A Philosopher Reading,” by a follower of David Teniers the Younger, 1610-1690 (Wikimedia Commons, 2024)
You can also download and read or share a .pdf of the complete text of this essay by scrolling down to the bottom of this post and clicking on the Download tab.
The Internal Structure of Reading and the Internal Structure of Philosophizing
For the purposes of this essay, by “philosophy” I’ll mean Western philosophy, from ancient Greek philosophy through Hellenistic and Roman philosophy, through medieval European, early modern European, modern European, and post-Kantian European and Anglo-American philosophy, right up to 6am this morning.[i] Literacy emerged in Sumeria roughly 5500 years ago, but the emergence of philosophy in ancient Greece roughly 2500 years ago seems to have been closely bound up with the emergence of the first alphabetic writing-&-reading system there in the 8th century BCE (Rayner et al., 2012: ch. 2). Certainly, in the 6th century BCE, the emergence of logic with Parmenides, Zeno, Plato, and Aristotle, and the more less simultaneous emergence of mathematics with the Pythagoreans and Euclid, as formal sciences, both require not only literacy but also alphabetic writing-&-reading and its specific grammar or syntax and semantics. And logic and mathematics—alongside various forms of naturalistic investigation and speculation (principally cosmological/physical or biological), various forms of religion and spirituality (principally existential/mystical or theological), and various forms of rule-governed conduct and sociality (principally ethical, moral, or political)—are the core ingredients of the emergent discipline of philosophy. But neither logic, nor mathematics, nor philosophy would be possible without the act or process of reading; and since writing presupposes reading—in order to write something, you have to be able to read what you’re writing[ii]—then reading is really the condition of the possibility of all philosophy, in the sense that reading is not only necessary but also essential to philosophy. Indeed, the philosophy of reading is first philosophy (Hanna, 2023a). Therefore, philosophy isn’t merely “the love of wisdom” (in Greek, philo + sophia), it’s fundamentally the love of wisdom that can be expressed in legible texts and read by oneself and others.
That all being so, then one would naturally expect there to be important analogies or even isomorphisms between, on the one hand, the internal structure of the act or process of reading, and on the other, the internal structure of philosophizing. And that’s what I want to investigate in this essay.[iii]
Here’s my analysis of reading, quoted (with a few redactions, indicated by inserted material in square brackets or ellipses) from an earlier essay:
For convenience and ease of expression, in what follows … I’m going to use the terms legible, legibility, illegible, and illegibility, respectively, as synonyms for the terms readable, readability, unreadable, and unreadability, respectively.
[Now] I’ll propose a set of fairly precise necessary and sufficient conditions for legibility and reading.
[A]ccording to the Oxford Encyclopedic English Dictionary, “character” is defined as
a printed or written letter, symbol, or distinctive mark. (Hawkins and Allen, 1991: p. 247)
In view of that, then I’ll … define a text as any sequence of one or more characters, where a one-character sequence is the lower-bound limiting case, and there’s no upper bound on the number of characters. In turn, what I’ll call a text-in-L is defined as any sequence of one or more characters belonging to a particular language L. It’s important to note that a language L can contain some characters (hence also some texts) that belong to one or more different languages L2, L3, L4, etc. So, for example, English contains some letters, words, and sentences belonging to other languages, including Greek, Latin, French, German, Italian, etc. Then, I’ll provide necessary and sufficient conditions for legibility in two parts, as follows:
1. A text T-in-L is legible if and only if T-in-L satisfies the perceptibility condition, the syntactic condition, and the semantic condition, and
2. all and only such texts-in-L have legibility.
The perceptibility condition says that the basic orientable (i.e., intrinsically directional, for example, up-down, back-front, or right-left) spatial shape and structure of T-in-L must be at least minimally perceptually detectable, i.e., that T-in-L must be at least partially perceptually detectable, hence it’s not completely perceptually undetectable, and thereby T-in-L is able-to-be-scanned to at least that minimal extent. For example, if a text is completely blacked out, erased, otherwise completely smudged out or obscured, invisibly small, or so big that its shape cannot be perceived, then it’s perceptually undetectable and illegible. But on the other hand, as it were, even if a text T-in-L is right-to-left<–>left-to-right mirror-reversed and turned upside down … it’s still able-to-scanned to the minimal extent that it’s not completely undetectable….
The syntactic condition says that T-in-L must be at least minimally well-formed, i.e., that T-in-L must be at least partially well-formed, hence it’s not completely ill-formed, and thereby T-in-L is able-to-be-parsed to at least that minimal extent. For example, even if a text T-in-L is perceptually detectable, it can be completely jumbled, completely misspelled, or completely ungrammatical, or its characters can be completely randomly distributed, and in any of those ways it would be syntactically illegible. Indeed, ciphers or secret codes (as opposed to hidden messages in otherwise legible texts) are designed to approach syntactic illegibility, on the working assumption that the more illegible they are, the harder they are to break; so if there are some ciphers that have never been broken and all their creators are dead, or, more thought-experimentally, if there were a cipher created by intelligent non-human aliens that, even in principle, could never be broken by rational human animals, then they would be illegible in the syntactic sense. Therefore, a text-in-L’s satisfying the perceptibility condition, as such, is not itself independently sufficient for readability and thus it’s not itself independently sufficient for being the target of any actual or possible act or process of reading.
And the semantic condition says that the conceptual content and/or essentially non-conceptual content of T-in-L must be at least minimally coherent, i.e., that the conceptual content and/or essentially non-conceptual content of T-in-L must be at least partially coherent, hence not completely incoherent, and thereby the conceptual content and/or essentially non-conceptual content of T-in-L is able-to-be comprehended to at least that minimal extent. For example, even if a text is minimally perceptible and also minimally well-formed, nevertheless it can still violate minimal requirements of conceptual sortal correctness and/or essentially non-conceptual sortal correctness, or be strictly non-referential, and be semantic gibberish, hence be illegible in the semantic sense, like this non-poetical text-in-English, a paradigm case of sortal incorrectness, devised by Bertrand Russell (Russell, 1940: p. 166)—
quadruplicity drinks procrastination
or this famous poetical text-in-English, a paradigm case of strict non-referentiality, taken from Lewis Carroll’s Jabberwocky…—
‘Twas brillig, and the slithy toves
Did gyre and gimble in the wabe;
All mimsy were the borogoves,
And the mome raths outgrabe. (Carroll, 1988)
Therefore, that text from Jabberwocky’s satisfying the perceptibility condition together with the syntactic condition, yet also failing the semantic condition, shows that the first two conditions are not themselves conjointly sufficient for readability and thus that they’re not themselves conjointly sufficient for being the target of any actual or possible act or process of reading. Of course, millions of people, including you, the reader of this very essay, have in some sense or another “read” that text from Jabberwocky; but my way of explaining away this apparent inconsistency is just to point out that Jabberwocky is indeed legible in both the perceptible and synactic senses (so in two senses, readable), but illegible in the semantic sense (so in one sense, unreadable), hence not legible in all relevant senses, hence illegible by my contextual definition, or conceptual analysis, of legibility. The same point holds, mutatis mutandis, for “quadruplicity drinks procrastination” and all other essentially similar texts-in-L: you can “read” it in two senses (the perceptible sense and the syntactic sense), but strictly speaking, it’s illegible according to the necessary and sufficient conditions of legibility, precisely because it fails the semantic condition.
Assuming all of that so far, I’m now in a position to provide precise necessary and sufficient conditions for the act or process of reading. In the following contextual definition, or conceptual analysis, by person I mean rational human minded animal: namely, a living human organism that’s capable of (i) consciousness, (ii) self-consciousness, (iii) caring (i.e., desire, emotion, and feeling—the affects), (iv) sensible cognition, (v) intellectual cognition, (vi) volition, (vii) object-directed and act-directed intentionality more generally, and (viii) free agency. Then, I’ll provide necessary and sufficient conditions for reading in two parts, as follows:
1. A person P reads a text T-in-L if and only if P consciously or self-consciously at least minimally scans, at least minimally parses, and also at least minimally comprehends T-in-L, and
2. all and only such acts or processes are reading.
It’s important to note that, consistently with this contextual definition, or conceptual analysis, of reading, a person P can read a text T-in-L either aloud or silently to themselves. It’s also important to note that neither scanning, nor parsing, nor comprehending, need be self-consciously or reflectively performed: this can be done in a more-or-less or even altogether pre-reflectively or unself-consciously conscious way; indeed, we typically “look right through” what we’re reading in order to go directly to the meaning (whether sense, reference, or speech-act uptake) of what we’re reading, and altogether overlook the scanning, parsing, and comprehending dimensions of the act or process of reading itself. In order to bring those dimensions back into view, all you have to do is to repeat any text-in-L—for example, a sentence or word—out loud a few times (say, ten times) until it sounds strangely bereft of meaning; that strange absence-of-meaning has then become vividly manifest to you precisely because the perceptibility and syntax of that particular text-in-L have been temporarily self-consciously detached from what you’ve been previously been pre-reflectively and unself-consciously yet still consciously comprehending.
And it’s also important to note that the point I made above about “readers” of Jabberwocky and “quadruplicity drinks procrastination” goes, mutatis mutandis, for my contextual definition, or conceptual analysis, of reading: of course, millions of people, including you, the reader of this very essay, are in some sense or another “readers” of that text from Jabberwocky; and no doubt a few thousand people have read “quadruplicity drinks procrastination”; but my way of explaining away this apparent inconsistency too, is just to point out that Jabberwocky and “quadruplicity drinks procrastination” can indeed be read in both the perceptible and synactic senses (so in two senses, that’s reading), but cannot be read in the semantic sense (so in one sense, that’s not reading), hence it’s not reading in all the relevant senses, hence it’s not reading by my contextual definition, or conceptual analysis, of reading. (Hanna, 2023c: pp. 8 and 11-15)
My three-stage analysis of reading—as a complex act or process necessarily involving the ordered sub-operations of scanning, parsing, and comprehending—is generally confirmed by recent and contemporary empirical work in the cognitive psychology of reading (Rayner et al., 2012: chs. 4-9). So for the purposes of argument, let’s grant my analysis of the internal structure of reading. In studying beginning reading and the stages of reading development, contemporary cognitive psychologists of reading have also found it convenient to bundle the sub-operations of scanning and parsing into a single conjoint sub-operation they call decoding, as contrasted with the sub-operation of comprehension (Rayner et al., 2012: chs. 10-11). Phenomenologically considered, I do think that scanning can be fairly easily distinguished from parsing. For example, I’ve never learned or studied Japanese, so obviously I cannot read it. But by virtue of having watched quite a few Japanese movies with English subtitles, in which many and various Japanese texts are visually displayed, I can now at least minimally scan Japanese, but neither parse it nor comprehend it. Nevertheless, it’s not only theoretically convenient, but also philosophically illuminating, to treat scanning + parsing, i.e., decoding, as a single operational unity, as per contemporary cognitive psychology of reading development.
This latter point comes forward vividly when we consider reading disorders (Rayner et al., 2012: ch. 12). In view of the reading disorder of dyslexia, which is usually defined by psychologists of reading as sub-par performance in scanning-&-parsing (decoding) that can also be combined with competent or even high-level performance in comprehension, we can easily recognize that scanning + parsing (decoding) is distinct from comprehension. By instructive contrast, let’s also consider the reading disorder of hyperlexia, which is usually defined by psychologists of reading as competent or even high-level performance in scanning + parsing (decoding) accompanied by sub-par performance in comprehension. Again, this clearly and distinctly shows that scanning + parsing (decoding) is distinct from comprehension. Moreover, the related phenomena of early reading and late talking (aka “Einstein Syndrome”—see, e.g., Sowell, 1997; Smith-Garcia, 2020) are often hyperlexic. Hence comprehension can operate in an effective way (relatively) independently of scanning + parsing (decoding); and scanning + parsing (decoding) can operate in an effective way (relatively) independently of comprehension. Nevertheless competent, high-level, or even highest-level performance in both scanning-&-parsing (decoding) and comprehension are operatively independent of talking: Albert Einstein himself, who was reportedly a late talker but able to read competently by age 7 and also able to read advanced physics books by age 12, is a paradigmatic example.
With those distinctions in place, I’ll now try to map the internal structure of the act or process of reading onto the internal structure of the act or process of philosophizing, in five steps.
First, it seems clear and distinct that scanning + parsing (decoding) corresponds to logico-mathematical reasoning in philosophizing, or for short, philosophical analysis: roughly speaking, “bottom-up” philosophizing. Paradigmatic examples of philosophical analysis would be the works of Gottlob Frege, early Bertrand Russell, early G.E. Moore, early Ludwig Wittgenstein, and Rudolf Carnap (see, e.g., Hanna, 2021: chs. I-IX).
Second, it also seems clear and distinct that comprehension corresponds to synoptic understanding in philosophizing, or for short, philosophical synthesis: roughly speaking, “top-down” philosophizing. A paradigmatic example of philosophical synthesis would be the work of Ernst Cassirer (see, e.g., Luft, 2021).
Third, by analogy or isomophism with dyslexia, it’s really possible to have sub-par performance in philosophical analysis when combined with competent, high-level, or even highest-level performance in philosophical synthesis: indeed, this is obviously the case in 20th century post-structuralist or post-modernist Continental philosophy (see, e.g., Hanna, 2021: section XVII.5, 2022: section II). A paradigmatic example of the dyslexic condition of 20th century post-structuralist or post-modernist Continental philosophy would be Jacques Derrida’s Of Grammatology (Derrida, 1967/1976). It should be particularly noted that I’m neither saying nor suggesting that Derrida himself was dyslexic: that would be reverse ad hominem reasoning.[iv]
Fourth, by analogy or isomophism with hyperlexia, it’s also clearly possible to have have competent, high-level, or even highest-level performance in philosophical analysis, when combined with sub-par performance in philosophical synthesis: indeed, this is equally obviously the case in 20th century post-classical Analytic philosophy (see, e.g., Hanna, 2021: ch. XVII). A paradigmatic example of the hyperlexic condition of 20th century post-classical Analytic philosophy would be W.V.O. Quine’s Word and Object (Quine, 1960; see also Hanna, 2015: ch. 4, 2022: section III). Again, it should be particularly noted that I’m neither saying nor suggesting that Quine himself was hyperlexic, which would also be reverse ad hominem reasoning.
Fifth, when taken together, the four preceding analogies or isomorphisms between the internal structure of reading and the internal structure of philosophizing collectively strongly suggest
(i) that competent philosophizing, just like competent reading, which displays equal competence in scanning + parsing (decoding) and comprehension alike, should display equal competence in philosophical analysis and philosophical synthesis alike, as complementary philosophical sub-activities,
(ii) that good philosophizing, just like high-level performance in reading, which displays equal high-level performance in scanning + parsing (decoding) and comprehension alike, should display equal high-level performance in philosophical analysis and philosophical synthesis alike, as complementary philosophical sub-activities, and
(iii) that great philosophizing, just like highest-level performance in reading, which displays equal highest-level performance in scanning + parsing (decoding) and comprehension alike, should display equal highest-level performance in philosophical analysis and philosophical synthesis alike, as complementary philosophical sub-activities.
If the preceding argument is sound, then competent philosophy, good philosophy, and great philosophy, alike, should be neither “Continental,” which is inherently unstable and on a slippery slope towards a disordered dyslexic condition of philosophy, nor “Analytic,” which is also inherently unstable and on a slippery slope towards a disordered hyperlexic condition of philosophy. Instead, competent philosophizing, good philosophizing, and great philosophizing, alike, should all be dual or duplex—that is, they should all be in a dynamic, vital condition of bottom-up-&-top-down complementarity, coherently fusing logico-mathematical reasoning and synoptic understanding, philosophical analysis and philosophical synthesis—just like the properly-functioning complex human capacity for reading.
Paradigmatic examples of great philosophizing in this dynamic, vital dual or duplex condition would be Plato’s philosophy and also Aristotle’s philosophy in the classical ancient Greek, Hellenistic/Roman, and Medieval traditions; and in the early modern, modern, and post-Kantian traditions, Immanuel Kant’s Critical philosophy, especially including the Critique of Pure Reason (Kant, 1781/1787/1996; see also Hanna, 2001, 2006) and also later Wittgenstein’s philosophy, especially including the Philosophical Investigations (Wittgenstein, 1953; see also Hanna, 2021: chs. XI-XIV). Indeed, there are profound affinities and historical connections between Kant’s Critical philosophy and Wittgenstein’s philosophy, both early and late (Hanna, 2017). Therefore, by the criterion of great philosophizing in a dynamic, vital dual or duplex condition, The Big Four in the history of (Western) philosophy would be Plato, Aristotle, Kant, and Wittgenstein.
In the early 00s, by means of a bizarre mixture of postmortem diagnosis and reverse ad hominem reasoning, the well-known Finnish Analytic philosopher Jaakko Hintikka claimed that Wittgenstein was dyslexic (Hintikka, 2004). But Hintikka used a tendentious definition of “dyslexia,” focused on “a difficulty of consciously recognizing the rule one is following,” that wouldn’t be accepted by contemporary cognitive psychologists of reading:
[t]he term dyslexia is used to describe individuals who have difficulty reading words accurately and fluently. (Rayner et al., 2012: ch. 12)
And as far as I know, there’s no empirical evidence whatsoever that Wittgenstein had dyslexia in this sense: on the contrary, his reading skills were clearly of the highest level (see, e.g., Monk, 1990). So with all due respect to Hintikka, his claim is at best polemical and at worst, well, bullshit (Frankfurt, 1988). I mention it only as an instructively useful example of how not to do the philosophy of reading.
Therefore, with those Kantian and Wittgensteinian paradigms as normative guides, contemporary philosophers should resolutely commit themselves to philosophizing in a dynamic, vital dual or duplex condition, modelled on competent, high-level, and highest-level performance in reading, and thereby surpass and transcend Analytic philosophy and Continental philosophy alike. And if, as I proposed at the outset, philosophy is “fundamentally the love of wisdom that can be expressed in legible texts and read by oneself and others,” then this dynamic, vital dual or duplex, post-Analytic, post-Continental mode of philosophizing must also and above all be futuristic, by virtue of being aimed not only at contemporary readers, but also and above all at readers to come (Hanna, 2021: ch. XVIII, 2023d).[v]
NOTES
[i] Of course, there are also important non-Western traditions of philosophy: African, Asian, Indian, Indigenous, Middle Eastern, and so-on. But unfortunately, I’m not qualified to explore these. Nevertheless, it would be extremely interesting to know whether the internal structures of philosophizing I identify in Western philosophy, also hold up in non-Western philosophy, or not—and if not, why not.
[ii] To be sure, reading also presupposes that legible texts have already been written by someone. But the end or purpose of writing itself is to express, by means of legible texts, information that can be read by oneself or others. So all writing is inherently reading-centered or, neologistically put, lectiocentric.
[iii] There’s also a thick, rich, and substantive dimension of affect, embodiment, and agency in reading (Hanna, 2023b), that one would also naturally expect to have a direct bearing on the corresponding affective, embodied, and agential dimension of philosophy. I’ve discussed that dimension of philosophy in (Hanna, 2024).
[iv] By “reverse ad hominem reasoning,” I mean reasoning fallaciously from logical facts about arguments to personal facts about people who are putting forward those arguments, as opposed to standard ad hominem reasoning, which is reasoning fallaciously from personal facts about people who are putting forward arguments to logical facts about their arguments.
[v] I’m grateful to Elma Berisha and Scott Heftler for thought-provoking correspondence or conversation on and around the main topics of this essay.
REFERENCES
(Carroll, 1988). Carroll, L. Through the Looking-Glass. New York: Dial.
(Derrida, 1967/1976). Derrida, J. Of Grammatology. Trans. G.C. Spivak. Baltimore MD: Johns Hopkins Univ. Press.
(Frankfurt, 1988). Frankfurt, H. “On Bullshit.” In H. Frankfurt, The Importance of What We Care About. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press. Pp. 117-133.
(Hanna, 2001). Hanna, R. Kant and the Foundations of Analytic Philosophy. Oxford: Clarendon/Oxford Univ. Press. Also available online in preview HERE.
(Hanna, 2006). Hanna, R. Kant, Science, and Human Nature. Oxford: Clarendon/Oxford Univ. Press. Also available online in preview HERE.
(Hanna, 2015). Hanna, R. Cognition, Content, and the A Priori: A Study in the Philosophy of Mind and Knowledge. THE RATIONAL HUMAN CONDITION, Vol. 5. Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press. Also available online in preview HERE.
(Hanna, 2017). Hanna, R. “Wittgenstein and Kantianism.” In H.-J. Glock (ed.), Blackwell Companion to Wittgenstein. Oxford: Blackwell. Pp. 682-698. Also available online in preview at URL = <https://www.academia.edu/11716593/Wittgenstein_and_Kantianism>.
(Hanna, 2021). Hanna, R. The Fate of Analysis: Analytic Philosophy From Frege to The Ash-Heap of History. New York: Mad Duck Coalition. Affordably available in hardcover, softcover, and Epub at URL = <https://themadduckcoalition.org/product/the-fate-of-analysis/>.
(Hanna, 2022). Hanna, R. “Six Studies in The Decline and Fall of Professional Academic Philosophy, And a Real and Relevant Alternative.” Borderless Philosophy 5: 48-130. Available online at URL = <https://www.cckp.space/single-post/bp-5-2022-robert-hanna-six-studies-in-the-decline-and-fall-of-professional-philosophy-48-130>.
(Hanna, 2023a). Hanna, R. “The Philosophy of Reading as First Philosophy.” Unpublished MS. Available online at URL = <https://www.academia.edu/107390679/The_Philosophy_of_Reading_as_First_Philosophy_September_2023_version_>.
(Hanna, 2023b). Hanna, R. ““Dare to Read: Affect, Embodiment, and Agency in Reading.” Unpublished MS. Available online at URL = <https://www.academia.edu/107944223/Dare_to_Read_Affect_Embodiment_and_Agency_in_Reading_October_2023_version_>.
(Hanna, 2023c). Hanna, R. “Caveat Lector: From Wittgenstein to The Philosophy of Reading.” Unpublished MS. Available online HERE.
(Hanna, 2023d). Hanna, R. “Kantian Futurism.” Unpublished MS. Available online at URL = <https://www.academia.edu/104371052/Kantian_Futurism_December_2023_version_>.
(Hanna, 2024). Hanna, R. “What Good is Philosophy? My Answer.” Unpublished MS. Available online at URL = <https://www.academia.edu/97370379/What_Good_is_Philosophy_My_Answer_January_2024_version_>.
(Hawkins and Allen, 1991). Hawkins, J.M. and Allen, R. (eds.) The Oxford Encyclopedic English Dictionary. Oxford: Clarendon/Oxford Univ. Press.
(Hintikka, 2004). Hintikka, J. “Wittgenstein’s Demon and his Theory of Mathematics.” In T. Demeter (ed.), Essays on Wittgenstein and Austrian Philosophy. Leiden: Brill. Pp. 89-107. Available online at URL = <https://brill.com/display/book/9789004458437/B9789004458437_s007.xml>.
(Kant, 1781/1787/1997). Kant, I. Critique of Pure Reason. Trans. P. Guyer and A. Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1997. 1781 or A edition: Ak 4: 1-251; 1787 or B edition: Ak 3.
(Luft, 2021). Luft, S. “Cassirer’s Place in Today’s Philosophical Landscape.” In S. Truwant (ed.), Interpreting Cassirer. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press. Pp. 214-246. Available online at URL = <https://www.academia.edu/69821965/Cassirers_Place_in_Todays_Philosophical_Landscape>.
(Monk, 1990). Monk, R. Ludwig Wittgenstein: The Duty of Genius. London: Jonathan Cape.
(Quine, 1960). Quine, W.V.O. Word and Object. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.
(Rayner et al., 2012). Rayner, K., Pollatsek, A., Ashby, J., and Clifton Jr, C. Psychology of Reading. 2nd edn., New York: Psychology Press/Routledge.
(Russell, 1940). Russell, B. An Inquiry into Meaning and Truth. London: George Allen and Unwin.
(Smith-Garcia, 2020). Smith-Garcia, D. “Einstein Syndrome: Characteristics, Diagnosis, and Treatment.” Healthline. Available online at URL = <https://www.healthline.com/health/einstein-syndrome>.
(Sowell, 1997). Sowell, T. The Einstein Syndrome: Bright Children Who Talk Late. New York: Basic Books.
(Wikimedia Commons, 2024). Wikimedia Commons. “ ‘A Philosopher Reading,’ by a follower of David Teniers the Younger, 1610-1690.” Available online HERE.
(Wittgenstein, 1953). Wittgenstein, L. Philosophical Investigations. Trans. G.E.M. Anscombe. New York: Macmillan.
Against Professional Philosophy is a sub-project of the online mega-project Philosophy Without Borders, which is home-based on Patreon here.
Please consider becoming a patron!