Merleau-Ponty Meets The Kripke Monster Redux: The Essential Embodiment Theory Now, #2.

(Wikipedia, 2022a)

TABLE OF CONTENTS

0. Introduction

1. The Essential Embodiment Theory Briefly and Compactly Re-Presented and Re-Motivated

2.  Three Later Significant Elaborations and Extensions of The Essential Embodiment Theory: Natural Libertarianism, The Neo-Organicist Worldview, and The Metaphysics of Liberal Naturalism

3. One Cheer, But Only One, For Analytic Panpsychism

00. Concluding Semi-Autobiographical Quasi-Whiteheadian Postscript


This essay will be published in five installments; this second installment contains section 1.

You can also download and read or share a .pdf of the complete text of this essay, including the REFERENCES, HERE.


1. The Essential Embodiment Theory Briefly and Compactly Re-Presented and Re-Motivated

So that we’re all on the same page, I’ll begin this section with a quick critical synoptic sketch of recent and contemporary mainstream Analytic philosophy of mind (see, e.g., Chalmers, 1996; Kim, 2005, 2006).

As I see it, the two fundamental problems in recent and contemporary mainstream Analytic philosophy of mind are these:

The mind-body problem: what accounts for the existence and specific character of conscious, intentional minds like ours in a fundamentally physical world?

The problem of mental causation: what accounts for the causal efficacy and causal relevance of conscious, intentional minds like ours in a fundamentally physical world?

Correspondingly, there are two standard approaches to these problems: (i) dualist approaches and (ii) materialist or physicalist approaches. (I’ll also briefly discuss idealist approaches at the end of this section and in section 3.) 

Now, classical Cartesian interactionist substance dualism in the philosophy of mind[i]  holds that the human mind and the human body are essentially distinct substances: one of them fundamentally non-material or non-physical, and the other one fundamentally material or physical, hence fundamentally non-mental. These essentially distinct substances are held together by metaphysically mysterious contingent causal relations, including both mind-to-body or mind-to-mind causal relations (aka “mental causation”) and body-to-mind causal relations. From a classical Cartesian interactionist substance dualist point of view, only body-to-body causal relations are non-mysterious, although of course Hume thoroughly “problematized” that kind of causal relations too in his “unfortunate” Treatise (Hume, 1776/2022: p. 6), thereby setting the philosophical stage for Kant’s thrilling transcendental idealist modal-metaphysical rescuscitation of the very idea of manifestly real efficacious causation, via his conception of the synthetic a priori. In any case, there’s also a more cautious 20th and 21st century variant of classical Cartesian interactionist substance dualism, known as property dualism, which says that even though there aren’t, at least in the actual world, any Cartesian mental substances per se, nevertheless there are essentially distinct fundamentally mental properties and fundamentally physical properties, each of which can be instantiated without the other in conceivably and logically possible worlds, for example, in bodiless spiritual minds, or in mindless zombies that are particle-for-particle and behavior-for-behavior duplicates ofour actual-world minded bodies.

By sharp contrast, recent and contemporary mainstream Analytic philosophy of mind can be generally characterized by its official and orthodox rejection of classical Cartesian interactionist substance dualism, and correspondingly by its central, ongoing commitment to materialism or physicalism as regards the nature of the mind-body relation and mental causation. Materialism or physicalism, as such, says that all properties of or facts about the human mind are constitutively determined by fundamentally physical facts. But there are three interestingly different types of materialism or physicalism: (i) reductive materialism or physicalism, (ii) eliminative materialism or physicalism, and (iii) non-reductive materialism or physicalism. Reductive materialism or physicalism—a prime example of which is the mind-brain identity theory so famously criticized by Kripke in Naming and Necessity, as per the second epigraph of this essay (Kripke, 1972/1980: pp. 144-155)—says that all properties of or facts about the human mind are wholly constitutively determined by fundamentally physical properties or facts, or, as the technical terminology has it, mental properties or facts are logically supervenient on fundamentally physical properties or facts. That is: the human mind is really nothing over and above the fundamentally physical world. Eliminative materialism, by contrast, says that, given the truth of reductive materialism, minds are really nothing at all: our belief in the existence of minds is a mere illusory folk belief and a conceptual myth. Non-reductive materialism or physicalism, by another contrast, says that some but not all properties of or facts about the human mind are wholly constitutively determined by fundamentally physical properties or facts. That is: certain causally inert or epiphenomenal properties or facts about the human mind—for example, properties or facts about the normative character of rational human intentionality, or about the qualitative specific character of consciousness—vary independently of fundamentally physical properties or facts, even though all of the human mind’s causally efficacious properties or facts are still wholly constitutively determined by fundamentally physical facts.

At the same time, however, even despite its official anti-Cartesianism, this recent and contemporary mainstream Analytic materialist or physicalist tradition remains entirely but (mostly only) implicitly and unself-consciously committed to a three-part metaphysical presupposition that Maiese and I call Cartesian fundamentalism, according to which (i) the mental (if it indeed exists at all) is fundamentally (that is, inherently, necessarily, and exclusively) non-physical, (ii) the physical is fundamentally (that is, inherently, necessarily, and exclusively) non-mental, and (iii) no actual or possible substance has or can have a complementary dual essence that’s inherently and necessarily both mental and physical. Of course, Descartes himself was a Cartesian fundamentalist. But it’s crucial to recognize that the presupposition of Cartesian fundamentalism is also held by 20th and 21st century property dualists, like Kripke in Naming and Necessity, and Chalmers in The Conscious Mind, who both postulate the conceivable and logically possible existence of essentially distinct mental and physical substances—for example, bodiless spiritual minds in pain (“pains without brains”) and mindless, pain-lacking zombies (“brains without pains”)—even though neither of these  exists in the actual world. Indeed, all classical Cartesian interactionist substance dualists, 20th and 21st century property dualists, and also all reductive, eliminative, or non-reductive materialists or physicalists, alike, are committed to Cartesian fundamentalism. They differ among themselves only as to whether, on the one hand, EITHER mental and physical substances or mental and physical properties possess equal but opposite ontological status—which captures classical Cartesian interactionist substance dualism and 20th and 21st century property dualism—OR, on the other hand, the mental asymmetrically ontologically depends on the physical, or else is nothing but a folk-psychological illusion or conceptual myth—which captures reductive, eliminative, or non-reductive materialism or physicalism. Hence all reductive, eliminative, or non-reductive materialists or physicalists, at bottom, are Cartesian materialists or Cartesian physicalists, because they are fully committed to Cartesian fundamentalism, just like the classical Cartesian interactionist substance dualists and the 20th and 21st century property dualists.

 Although recent and contemporary mainstream Analytic philosophers of mind might well be “amazed” by this, the essential embodiment theory completely rejects Cartesian fundamentalism, and therefore it also completely rejects classical Cartesian interactionist substance dualism, 20th and 21st century property dualism, and also reductive, eliminative, and non-reductive materialism or physicalism, alike. Or, to play a riff on a most excellent Shakespearian curse: a philosophical plague on all their houses.

More positively and specifically, however, the essential embodiment theory says (i) that the physically irreducible conscious, intentional minds of minded animals are necessarily and completely embodied in those animals, and, more specifically, (ii) that the physically irreducible conscious, intentional mind of a minded animal is the global dynamic immanent structure of the living organismic body of that very animal, a structure that synchronously activates and guides that animal’s causally efficacious biological powers—or as Aristotle puts it in his own terminology: “the soul (anima) is the first actuality of a natural body that has life potentially” (Aristotle, 1968: II.i.412a22). Hence, as I mentioned in the Introduction, the essential embodiment theory is committed to a non-equilibrium-thermodynamics-inspired version of neo-Aristotelian hylomorphism about the mind-body relation.

According to the essential embodiment theory, consciousness is subjective experience, which is to say that it inherently involves a self that’s egocentrically-centered in orientable space and unidirectional time (= subjectivity), and also that this self enacts or engages in mental acts, states, or processes of various kinds (= experience), and furthermore consciousness has two basic modes: (i) pre-reflective or non-self-conscious consciousness, which, in being naturally directed towards cognitive or intentional targets other than itself, is immanently reflexive, or aware of itself egocentrically and subjectively, without implicitly or explicitly forming judgments or propositional thoughts about itself, and (ii) reflective consciousness, or self-consciousness, which, in being naturally directed towards, or about, itself AS a cognitive or intentional target, is aware of itself allocentrically and objectively, by implicitly or explicitly forming judgments or propositional thoughts about itself. More simply put, pre-reflective or non-self-consciousness consciousness is just being a conscious mind that’s directed towards other animals or things; whereas reflective or self-conscious consciousness is thinking about itself AS a conscious mind that’s ALSO directed towards other animals or things.

Against that theoretical backdrop, the essential embodiment theory is a specially restricted version of “dual-aspectism.” For other dual aspect theories, one can compare and contrast Spinoza’s theological dual-aspect monism (in The Ethics), Bertrand Russell’s neutral dual-aspect monism (in The Analysis of Mind and The Analysis of Matter), or A.N. Whitehead’s panexperientialist organicist dual-aspect monism (in Process and Reality—and I’ll briefly come back to that in the Conclusion). By contrast to those three kinds of dual-aspectism, the essential embodiment theory is committed to a dual-aspect monism of complex dynamic systems, and says that in all and only appropriately complex kinds of organismic living systems, causally efficacious physically irreducible mental properties and organismic physical properties are related by two-way necessary complementarity and neo-Aristotelian hylomorphism. Or in other and fewer words: physically irreducible minds are forms of life, and nothing in nature that’s not a form of life is minded.

To summarize so far: the essential embodiment theory says (i) that physically irreducible minds like ours are necessarily and completely embodied, (ii) that physically irreducible minds like ours are complex dynamic global structures of our living organismic bodies, i.e., forms of life, (iii) that physically irreducible minds like ours are therefore inherently alive, (iv) that physically irreducible minds like ours are therefore inherently causally efficacious, just like all forms of organismic life, and (v) that physically irreducible minds like ours emerge over time and in space in all and only certain kinds of living organisms, i.e., minded animals.

Furthermore, if by autonomy we mean a capacity for self-determination in the broadest possible sense, then we can also distinguish between (v1) the autonomy of proto-consciousness, a minimal and relatively self-less endogenous sensibility possessed by all living organisms, all the way down to unicellular organisms, (v2) the autonomy of pre-reflective consciousness, an egocentric and immanently self-aware, self-locating sensibility possessed by all minded animals, and (v3) the autonomy of self-consciousness, a further and specifically rational conscious capacity to represent oneself by means of concepts and judgments, which requires and indeed presupposes that we’re also able to think propositionally, speak richly-structured natural languages, and engage in logical reasoning (Hanna, 2006b: ch. 4).

Now in addition to self-consciousness, rational human minded animals  are not only inherently capable of (i) consciousness, that is, subjective experience (as defined above), but also of (ii) intentionality, that is, directedness to all kinds of things as their cognitive, desiderative, emotional, etc., targets. More generally, consciousness and intentionality are complementary: they’re distinct capacities, but also necessarily mutually connected capacities. More specifically, necessarily, all conscious acts, states, or processes are also intentional acts, states, or processes (this is also sometimes called “the intentionality of phenomenology”) and all intentional acts, states, and processes are also conscious acts, states, or processes (this is also sometimes called “the phenomenology of intentionality”). Our complementary capacities for consciousness and intentionality are also shared with minded animals in many other species, but are self-evidently phenomenologically manifest in minds like ours, via our further capacity for specifically rational consciousness, intentionality, and self-consciousness, not only as per Descartes’s Cogito, “I think, therefore I am,” but also, and even more fundamentally, via our capacity for essentially embodied affective and emotional consciousness, intentionality, and self-consciousness, as per what Maiese and I call The Essentially Embodied Cogito, “I desire, therefore I am” (Maiese and Hanna, 2009: p. 21).

In view of all that, here are eight reasons why the essential embodiment theory not only dissolves the mind-body problem and the problem of mental causation, but also finally solves them.

First, the essential embodiment theory fully avoids reducing the mental to the physical, i.e., it fully avoids reductive materialism or physicalism. Reductive materialism or physicalism, as we’ve seen, ends up in eliminativism. But what could be more phenomenologically or epistemically primitive than our subjective experience of ourselves as conscious, intentional minds, and correspondingly, what then could be more metaphysically and ontologically primitive than the fact of the mental quâ mental?

Second, the essential embodiment theory also fully avoids non-reductive materialism or physicalism and solves the problem of mental causation. Non-reductive materialism or physicalism entails the causal inertness of the mental or epiphenomenalism, hence it robs the mental of all its efficacious causal power. By a diametric contrast, the essential embodiment theory identifies the causal efficacy of physically irreducible minds with the causally efficacious powers of appropriately complex dynamic organismic systems. It is no theoretical virtue of epiphenomenalism that the mental still has “causal relevance” even though it has no causal efficacy. On the contrary, for mental causation to be really possible, the mental has got to have efficacious causal powers of its own, not merely an important informational bearing on causally efficacious fundamentally physical processes. According to the essential embodiment theory, physically irreducible minds like ours have efficacious causal powers of their own precisely insofar as they’re forms of life, and therefore synchronous structuring guidance-causes of appropriately complex dynamic organismic systems, i.e., our “human, all-too-human” minded animal bodies.

Third, by means of its solution to the problem of mental causation, the essential embodiment theory provides adequate metaphysical foundations for a robust metaphysics of free agency that I’ll briefly present in section 2 below.

Fourth, the essential embodiment theory also fully avoids reducing the physical to the mental, aka subjective idealism. Subjective idealism makes nature’s existence radically dependent on the existence of individual minds. But it’s highly implausible to hold that physical nature came into existence only after there were any minded animals. For, since animals are parts of physical nature, it would follow that animals came into existence only after there were minded animals. And it’s equally highly implausible to hold that if all individual minds were to perish, nature would go out of existence too. For in that case, since all animals die, and in most cases after animals die, their corpses continue to exist for a while, it would follow that necessarily, the last minded animal would have no corpse.

Fifth, the essential embodiment theory also fully avoids making the mental and the physical either essentially or even logically independent of one another, as per either Cartesian interactionist substance dualism or 20th and 21st century property dualism. Any form of dualism makes it impossible to explain how the mental and the physical causally interact without appealing to some sort of metaphysical mystery: for example, Descartes’s God, Leibniz’s divine pre-established harmony, an ectoplasmic medium, etc., etc. And any form of dualism also entails the synthetic a priori metaphysical impossibilities (i) that subjective experiences could ever exist without embodiment in living animal bodies like ours, (ii) that living animal bodies like ours could ever exist without subjective experiences. According to the essential embodiment theory, spirits and zombies alike are synthetic a priori or strongly metaphysically impossible, even though they’re also analytically or logically possible.

Sixth, the essential embodiment theory also fully avoids over-restricting mentality to the brain, i.e., it fully avoids the error of “the brain-bounded mind” (Hanna, 2011).

Seventh, the essential embodiment theory also fully avoids over-extending the mental beyond living animal bodies like ours, i.e., it avoids the error of “the extended mind” (Clark and Chalmers, 1998; Clark, 2008; Gallagher, 2011).

Eighth, and perhaps most importantly, building on the sixth and seventh points,   the essential embodiment theory is an approach to the mind-body relation and mental causation that’s perfectly scaled to the nature, scope, and limits of our “human, all too human” existence in a thoroughly nonideal natural and social world. Brain-boundedness falls short of the human condition: it makes us much less than we manifestly are. The extended mind exceeds the human condition: it makes us more than we manifestly are. Only the essential embodiment theory adequately captures and reflects the rational human condition: it tells us exactly what we manifestly really are. For I just am my rational minded animal body and its “human, all too human” life, for better or worse. In short, of all the mind-body theories out there (in all the gin joints in all the towns in all the world), only the essential embodiment theory conforms to Socrates’s Delphic-Oracle-inspired thesis that the ultimate aim of philosophy is to “know thyself.”

So, three cheers for the essential embodiment theory.

NOTES

[i] There’s also a 21st century variant on this, developed by E.J. Lowe, called “non-Cartesian substance dualism,” which postulates a person-body substance dualism, that I’ll leave aside for the purposes of this essay, since it also entails property dualism, which I’ll briefly critically discuss in this section, whose falsity entails the negation of Lowe’s non-Cartesian version of substance dualism by modus tollens.


Against Professional Philosophy is a sub-project of the online mega-project Philosophy Without Borders, which is home-based on Patreon here.

Please consider becoming a patron!