APP Editor’s Note
The following essay, Vadim Chaly’s “Immanuel Kant–Racist and Colonialist?,” was originally published in the Kantian Journal 39 (2020): 94-98.
You can also download or read a complete .pdf of this essay, in both English and Russian, HERE.
Vadim Chaly is Professor of Philosophy at Immanuel Kant Baltic Federal University in Kaliningrad, Russia.
You can read more about him and his work HERE.
The Afterword, by Robert Hanna, has been partially adapted from these two essays:
1. R. Hanna, “Kant and Cosmopolitanism Reconsidered,” Critique (2018), available online at URL =<https://virtualcritique.wordpress.com/2018/02/25/kant-and-cosmopolitanism-reconsidered/>.
2. Z, “Multi-Culti Is Anti-Kanti,” Against Professional Philosophy (23 November 2017), available online at URL = <https://againstprofphil.org/multi-culti-is-anti-kanti/>.
I. Immanuel Kant – Racist and Colonialist?, by Vadim Chaly
A murder of an Afro-American detainee by a policeman at the end of May 2020 caused a public outrage in the United States, which led to a campaign against the monuments to historical figures whose reputation, according to the protesters, was marred by racism. Some German publicists, impressed by the campaign, initiated an analogous search for racists among the national thinkers and politicians of the past. Suddenly Kant emerged as a ‘scapegoat’. This statement is an attempt to assess such reactions from the perspective of Russia’s experience.
In November 2018 Kant’s monument in Kaliningrad was attacked with pink paint and strewn with leaflets calling Kant an enemy and urging students to protest against the local university’s use of Kant’s name. The global media eagerly absorbed the photos of ‘pink Kant’. By the time the news reached its audience, the monument was restored to its normal condition in which it has since safely remained, but the deed was done and the global public unequivocally condemned the act of vandalism in Russia. The Russian public did so, too, but they differed in opinion whether this was a genuine act of spontaneous vandalism, or a special propaganda operation.
Over a year passed and the situation changed. Now the progressive public are the attackers of the monuments – of both those in bronze and those printed on paper. In the USA the confederates and Jefferson fell victims to the statue-toppling campaign as did Cervantes, while in the German press Kant is again accused of racism. What brings together the Western critics, blending Kant with confederate generals and colonial moguls, and the Russian paint-throwers proclaiming him an enemy?
First there is ressentiment, insensitive to arguments and directed at anything that scratches against the sore consciousness. It can seem spontaneous and “authentic” when expressed by a crowd toppling a monument, or mostly feigned when adopted by a certain admiral, obliged by his position to transmit a particular complex of emotions from above (Kant would have excused the admiral’s salvo as a private use of what could be called reason). But this is still the same phenomenon described by Nietzsche and Scheler and again rearing its head. It is imaginary revenge for the long lasting injustice, the real elimination of which requires much thought, endurance and calm confidence in one’s rightness. Throwing paint at a monument or its toppling by an emotional crowd is not a solution to the problem, but a symptom of wounded impotence, a recognition of one’s own inability to solve the problem by taking it to court, creating one if necessary.
Second is the unabashed immediacy with which current standards and conventions are applied to historical figures. To the admiral, Kant was a “traitor of his motherland” because in 1758 he assumed Russian citizenship instead of calling to arms or starting a resistance, and he “grovelled to obtain a chair” in his letter to the Russian empress. The fact that the forms of loyalties and identities, as well as the norms of writing and courtesy, were vastly different in the 18th century than they are today did not occur to the speaker, because his performative act pursued agendas beyond accuracy and truth. Although far more nuanced and careful, some of the present attacks on Kant follow the same template. The ideas of the eighteenth century are judged by current standards which themselves were made possible by the development of these very ideas. This either signifies the neglect of thoroughness in argumentation or reveals that the purpose of the critics, just as that of the admiral, is not truth but the consolidation and channelling of ressentiment to fuel this or that political agenda, served by this or that newspaper editorial.
To the readers who do not judge Kant by the newspapers his racism is old news. It has been discussed in the philosophical literature for decades and does indeed present a serious challenge. For Kant’s racism is, arguably, not a remnant peripheral prejudice in the worldview of the otherwise brilliant thinker, but a systematic part of his theoretical statement regarding the natural development of humanity. Criticising and overcoming this statement, not least from the platform of Kant’s own moral philosophy, is an important theoretical task carrying practical implications. But this task has nothing to do with the anti-monument campaign and cannot be accomplished by its means. On the contrary, such campaigns inhibit progress by inviting those infected with ressentiment to ‘enrich’ the discussion with their methods. Granted, some good can be made from bringing at least a portion of the public’s attention to the impressive conceptual work already accomplished by scholars criticising racist tendencies in Kant and the Enlightenment in general. But this is overshadowed by the harm done by the immediate and simplistic association of Kant with racism in the eyes of the general public. If one of the greatest Western thinkers is little more than a racist who also happened to write “incomprehensible books” on other utterly boring subjects, what can save Western philosophy?
Ressentiment and primitivism aside, there are conceptual similarities between the two positions that seem especially vivid from a Russian perspective. Russian philosophy long before critical theory, postcolonialism and decolonization noticed the colonial component of Western Enlightenment. To some Russian thinkers this constituted the essence of Western modern philosophy as such, and particularly that of Kant. Western reason, colonising Russian being, subjugating it to an alien form, replacing Russian communitarianism and religiosity (whether real or imaginary) with the autonomy of rational individualism and the industrial capitalist order, was the target of criticism in Russia at least since the early nineteenth century. The most radical of the Slavophiles went as far as seeing the Russian modern state itself as the chief instrument of Western colonisation. The epoch initiated by Peter the Great, and still ongoing, divided the Russians into a westernised minority of the exploiters, a “comprador elite”, and the exploited people subsisting on the shrinking remains of traditional ways of life. The artificial barrier between the two proved comparable to that between races, and the position of Russian peasant serfs was not much different from that of the African slaves of the West. On such a view, the catch-up modernisation of Russia was in fact double colonisation, external and internal, and German philosophy was essentially a tool of oppression. Kant provided not only for the Western guns of Krupp but also for the batons of Russian police and the shape of Russian jails. Thus, the pink paint on Kant’s monument was not an accident but an echo of a long standing debate.
The objections to this view in Russia are as old and will certainly sound familiar. They state that humanity has a common cosmic destiny, that we are subject to the same normative ideas and that these universal ideas acquire being only through the variety of particular races, nations and human personalities. However, such particularism has to rely on universalism to secure the basis for a peaceful proliferation of plurality. And this universalism is drawn from the universality of human reason and the capacity for compassion and love. Admittedly, Kant was not a champion of love, but he certainly was the champion of reason. The alternative to reason is obscurantism, the intellectual poverty of which forces its adherents to immerse themselves into two states. One is the state of riot, in which resentful and thoughtless mobs crush whatever they have failed to understand and overcome. The Russian revolution of 1917 and the Stalinist reaction offer an example of this path, and Russia’s present is still carrying the burden of this historical choice. The other is the state of acceptance and glorification of whatever negligence one happens to possess and whatever contradictory and bloodthirsty ideology is offered by one’s “own” and “true” state, party, ethnic group, or religious sect. Acceptance and glorification of whatever we already are and vehement criticism of enlightenment and education as attempts at colonisation or oppression of one’s identity doom us to smugness and degradation in self-incurred immaturity. This path was also well-travelled in Russian philosophy throughout the nineteenth century.
Russian experiences show that today’s Western radicals, discarding the “philosophy of dead white males” and its universalist reason from what they take to be moral perspectives, foredoom themselves to these conditions of riot and smugness. However, the refined public causes far more surprise when it opts for the policy of appeasement, or is overtaken by empathy towards the protesters, or gets carried away by what it mistakes for a fun game of statue-toppling or takes for a career opportunity, or, conversely, accepts the guilt and kneels in front of a mob. From an outsider’s point of view this seems like a capitulation to ressentiment and has nothing to do with the elimination of evil done by racism and racists. On the contrary, this capitulation to immaturity means abandoning one of the very few positions from which it is possible today to forcefully argue, lawfully demand and practically organise the consistent and thorough eradication of racism. If we wish to climb on the shoulders of giants like Kant and see further than they did, it makes sense not to overthrow them or spray their monuments with bright paint, not to detest or worship them, but try to understand them, paying due respect to their discoveries as well as overcoming their errors.
II. Afterword, by Robert Hanna
Vadim Chaly’s argument speaks for itself. But I also wanted to add two points by way of further elaboration and support.
First, in her thoroughly excellent, prize-winning 2012 book, Kant and Cosmopolitanism: The Philosophical Ideal of World Citizenship (Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 2012), henceforth “K&C,” Pauline Kleingeld critically and frankly, but at the same time charitably and even-handedly, discusses Kant’s racism and sexism:
[U]ntil the early 1790s [Kant] openly and explicitly defended a racial hierarchy according to which “whites” were the only non-deficient race. His 1780s theory of race was forcefully attacked by several of his contemporaries, most notably by Georg Foster, who had sailed around the world with Captain Cook and who regarded Kant’s race theory as empirically mistaken and his racial hierarchy as morally odious. It took Kant until the mid-1790s to change his mind and shift to an egalitarian position on race…. [T]he fact that he had second thoughts on race in the mid 1790s has gone entirely unnoticed. A proper understanding of Kant’s theory of race, especially his embrace of a racial hierarchy in the 1780s, sheds new light on his cosmopolitanism of this period, because his racial hierarchy also informs his ideal of the “cosmopolitan condition.” Kant’s change of mind on race, in the mid 1790s, leads to a more egalitarian and more consistent form of cosmopolitanism that allows him to create more room, within the parameters of morality and right, for cultural diversity. (K&C, pp. 7-8, boldfacing added)
[U]ntil the very end of his writing life, Kant insisted that women should be denied full and active citizenship status because of their “natural” inferiority and the “mental deficiences in their cognitive power”.… In other words, despite Kant’s gender-neutral description of the world citizenship of all human beings (Menschen), he does not envision women as being on a par with men. (K&C, p. 183, boldfacing added)[i]
In the same critical and frank, but also charitable and even-handed spirit, I will add that Kant was personally prejudiced against blind people, and therefore an ableist. For example, a blind student of Kant’s, A.F.J. Baczko, wrote that
Kant, who—I do not know for what reason—had an aversion to blind people, was so good to visit me. He confessed this aversion to me, adding that I was not blind because I possessed sufficient concepts from intuition and instruments, which overcame the lack of sight.[ii]
It is important to note that Kant very kindly visited his blind student, and very frankly confessed his own ableist prejudice to him. How many of us are capable of that?
But even if Kant was indeed personally biased in several ways—which of course makes him a morally bad and flawed, “human, all-too-human” person in those respects—it simply does not follow that his metaphysics, epistemology, philosophy of science, ethics, aesthetics, political philosophy, or moral theology are in any way morally bad or objectively false. That would be an obvious instance of the classical ad hominem fallacy of illegitimately arguing from facts about a person to facts about the views held by that person.
Second, and following up on that very point, what do you think of the following argument?
ARGUMENT 1
(i) E.T. is a fictional philosopher.
(ii) E.T. is an alien of indeterminate gender who is personally biased against women, non-white races, non-Europeans, and blind people.
(iii) Therefore, E.T.’s metaphysics, epistemology, philosophy of science, ethics, aesthetics, political philosophy, and moral theology are all morally bad and objectively false.
As a philosopher in particular, and as a critical reasoner more generally, there’s a flashing light going off in your mind saying:
Non sequitur! Non sequitur! Non sequitur!
For obviously, it’s a shining example of the classical ad hominem fallacy I mentioned above— the illegitimate inference from facts about a person to facts about the views held by that person — now updated in a specifically contemporary multiculturalist version, right?
No matter what our morally critical views about E.T.’s regrettable moral character might be, they couldn’t be rationally based on her/his/their merely being an alien of indeterminate gender, since s/he/they had no control over that, nor could any morally or critical conclusions we would be rationally entitled to draw about E.T.’s philosophical views in step (iii) be based either on personal characteristics over which E.T. had no control or on her/his/their regrettable moral character.
Now let’s consider the following argument —
ARGUMENT 2
(i) Immanuel Kant was an actual philosopher.
(ii) Immanuel Kant was male, white, European, short, prone to frequent chest pains, and personally biased against women, non-white races, non-Europeans, and blind people.
(iii) Therefore, Immanuel Kant’s metaphysics, epistemology, philosophy of science, ethics, aesthetics, political philosophy, and moral theology are all morally bad and objectively false.
Why are so many contemporary professional academic philosophers, and many others, strongly tempted to believe that ARGUMENT 2 is an acceptable bit of reasoning, when they wouldn’t have even the slightest temptation to believe that ARGUMENT 1 is rationally acceptable?
Indeed, it might seem to be simply gob-smacking that contemporary professional academic philosophers who would instantly spot the occurrence of an ad hominem fallacy in ARGUMENT 1, would be almost completely oblivious to its occurrence in ARGUMENT 2.
So what’s going on here?
What explains the rationally unhealthy attraction of contemporary academic professional philosophers, and many others, to ARGUMENT 2?
Surely, it couldn’t be merely because, unlike the fictional philosopher E.T., Kant was actual, male, white, European, short, and prone to frequent chest pains.
— Because that, of course, would be racist, sexist, xenophobic, sizeist, and ableist.
Not to mention anti-actualist.
My own view is that the ad hominem–based multiculturalist critique of Kant is ultimately driven by a much deeper and older trend in late 18th, 19th, 20th, and 21st century philosophy, and in the larger intellectual, social, and political context that has surrounded it: anti-Kantianism, by which I mean an intense and rationally-unjustified aversion to Kant, and to Kant’s or Kantian philosophy, in view of the fact that Kant is simply the most important and radically “dangerous” of the early modern, modern, and late modern Enlightenment philosophers,[iii] –and in that respect, only Spinoza and Marx are comparably important and radically “dangerous.”
In other words, the multiculturalist critique of Kant is itself driven by an intellectual, social, and even political prejudice that is at least 240 years old.
So I’ll end by reiterating, with gusto, Professor Chaly’s concluding observation:
If we wish to climb on the shoulders of [intellectual, sociocultural, and even political] giants like Kant and see further than they did, it makes sense not to overthrow them or spray their monuments with bright paint, not to detest or worship them, but try to understand them, paying due respect to their discoveries as well as overcoming their errors.
NOTES
[i] See also P. Kleingeld, “The Problematic Status of Gender-Neutral Language in the History of Philosophy: The Case of Kant,” Philosophical Forum 25 (1993): 134–150, available online at URL = <http://www.rug.nl/research/portal/files/3316343/Problematic_status.pdf>.
[ii] M. Kuehn, Kant: A Biography (Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 2001), p. 213.
[iii] See, e.g., R. Hanna, “The Kant Wars and The Three Faces of Kant,” Contemporary Studies in Kantian Philosophy 5 (2020): 73-94, available online at URL = <https://www.cckp.space/single-post/2020/06/15/CSKP5-2020-The-Kant-Wars-and-The-Three-Faces-of-Kant>.
Against Professional Philosophy is a sub-project of the online mega-project Philosophy Without Borders, which is home-based on Patreon here.
Please consider becoming a patron!